In a proposition, one component may be singled out as the one which matters, while the rest of the proposition is taken for granted. The proposition of the reply in a and b takes it for granted that someone broke the window and only focuses on the identity of the agent.

. Your son broke the window. —
a.No, it wasn't my son who broke the window.
b.No, it was your daughter who broke the window.

The component of a proposition that currently matters is its focus, while the rest of the proposition is presupposed. The material coding the presupposed portion is extrafocal.

At the level of discourse structure and the speaker's communicative intentions, focusing on one particular component of a proposition may serve different purposes. Two general functions may be distinguished which are regularly reflected in linguistic structure:

The replies in illustrate insistent focus. Their alternatives in illustrate suspensive focus.

. Your son broke the window. —
a.No, the one who broke the window wasn't my son.
b.No, the one who broke the window was your daughter.

and illustrate the most explicit variety of focus constructions, which is clefting. Some languages like English require such a high-level syntactic operation to place the focal component in the initial or final position of a clause. In other languages with freer word order, it suffices to place the focal component in either of these two clause positions (f).

.Yístekö́chikt-á=wa̱ukábatawa.
Cabecar1.SGERGpigkill-PFV=EFFarrowINSTR
I killed the pig with an arrow.(González & Lehmann 2024)
.Tá̱i̱=wa̱jekasirisu̱-á̱jé=ska.
Cabecarmuch-INTNS1.SG.ERGpeccarysee-PFVD.MED=LOC
I saw many peccaries there.(González & Lehmann 2024)

In any case, the focal component bears emphatic stress.